Information

Is this some form of cabbage?

Is this some form of cabbage?


We are searching data for your request:

Forums and discussions:
Manuals and reference books:
Data from registers:
Wait the end of the search in all databases.
Upon completion, a link will appear to access the found materials.

I would appreciate if someone could identify this plant. It's tall, but not very difficult to pull from the ground, and it has yellow flowers in large groups. I was told it's not mustard. Is it wild cabbage, and if so, what variety?

Location: western Illinois, in a garden.

Season: it's late April, and their roots are now rotting.

Height: I think they were around 3 feet.

More pictures:


The Brassicaceae family (of which cabbage and mustard are members) has a characteristic pattern of flowers - each flower has four equal sized petals, arranged in a cross-shape hence their other name - crucifers.

[h/t wikimedia commons]

It's not easy to see from your photos whether this is true, but I'm going to say, yes, it does look like a member of the Brassicaceae family. The cross-shape of the petals would confirm this.

I don't think these plants are native to Illinois, and it also does look somewhat like a crop plant, rather than a weed, so maybe it is an escape from a farm/garden. It could be canola, possibly.

Wild cabbages are native to the Mediterranean and Atlantic coasts of Europe , so it is probably not a wild cabbage, unless someone planted it in Illinois.


@JonathanMoore is correct, this is indeed a Brassica species. The brassica family (Brassicaceae) is a quite diverse family with something like 370 genera and 4000 species. They are found world-wide (apart from Antarctica, although Tryggve Gran tried mostly unsuccessfully to grow Sea Kale during the Terra Nova Expedition to the South Pole). You likely walk past several different types of Brassicaceae every day without knowing that they are there as they are common weeds of untended areas and will take advantage of small cracks in footpaths/pavement to grow.

There are a number of species that are common garden weeds throughout the world. They include many varieties of the Brassica rapa species (known for bok choi, Napa cabbage, choi sum and turnips amongst others, and is known for the oil "canola/colza").

In particular there is one variety called field mustard (Brassica rapa var. rapa, AKA common mustard, wild mustard, wild rutabaga, rape mustard) that is very commonly spread among gardens by its abundant seeding.

It has the long narrow leaves and the clusters of bright yellow flowers characteristic of the Brassica rapa group. However, the Brassica species commonly cross-pollinate and produce mixed varieties, so it is quite difficult to pin down exactly which one you have.


Is this some form of cabbage? - Biology

Scientific name: Symplocarpus foetidus
Common name:
Skunk Cabbage

(Information in this Species Page was compiled by Rachel Lang in Biology 220W, Spring 2006, at Penn State New Kensington)

Skunk cabbage (also called &ldquoclumpfoot cabbage&rdquo, &ldquoswamp lantern&rdquo, and &ldquopolecat weed&rdquo) is a large, flowering plant of wetlands. It is a member of the Arum plant family (which also includes Jack-in-the-Pulpit and some philodendrons). It is found in wet woodlands, marshes, and alongside streams over most of the eastern and Midwestern sections of United States and Canada north of the Carolinas and south of Nova Scotia).

Appearance
The tall, distinctive, enveloping spathe of S. foetidus arises from the ground in late February or early March often pushing up through the covering snow. This structure is typically the first sign of plant life in the woods after the long, gray, winter season. The spathe (which is a highly modified leaf) is brownish-purple and often streaked with yellow and red. Through the folds of the spathe, you can see the cluster of yellow flowers (the spadix) and can appreciate the extent of the protective encasement around it. The other leaves unfold in a broad spiral from the base of plant after the structure of spathe has faded. These leaves are green and quite long and broad (anywhere from 2 to 4 feet long and up to 1 foot wide). The above ground mass of the plant can stand 3 or 4 feet tall and spreads out to over-cover a substantial square footage of the soil surface.

At the center of the plant there is a short, round central root mass (a rhizome) out of which the leaves arise and from which the extensive root system forms. The roots are each about a quarter of inch in diameter and extend out from the rhizome mass in large numbers and in all directions. They grow unbranched for several feet and then terminate in an extensive system of fibrous rootlets. They solidly anchor the plant into the often loose, mucky soil. It is very difficult or even impossible to pull or even dig a skunk cabbage out of its soil foundation. The roots have circular surface ridges which grab onto the soil matrix and via root contractions actually help to pull the growing plant deeper and deeper into the soil system. Older plants, then, are rooted more deeply than younger plants. This contractile root adaptation may also help to prevent frost heaving of the plant out of the freezing and thawing wet soil matrix. The root system has been described as being &ldquovirtually indestructible&rdquo and may persist for decades and, possibly, even hundreds of years. The roots are also important storage sites for the accumulated polysaccharides from photosynthesis. These energy molecules are used by the plant each year for its flowering and growth and also for the production of heat (described below).

A Warm - Blooded Plant!
Skunk cabbage begins its yearly cycle on our Nature Trail in late February. The column of flowers (the spadix) and its enveloping spathe push up through the snow and ice down in a small wetland by the stream near the bridge. The plant is able to push up through the frozen soil and snow and maintain its tissue integrity even in very cold air temperatures because of its ability to metabolically generate heat. The spadix is the center of this remarkable catabolic event. Enzymes (&ldquoalternative oxidative enzymes&rdquo (AOX)) use atmospheric oxygen to rapidly breakdown stored root polysaccharides with the subsequent generation of heat. During the two weeks or so of spathe emergence and spadix flowering, a skunk cabbage plant will use as much oxygen as a comparably sized mammal in order to keep this heat generation system running. Further, the spadix is able to homeostatically control the activity of AOX through temperature monitoring and can, thus, keep its intra-spathe temperature not only up to 20 degrees C warmer than the surrounding environment but can also keep this temperature constant and optimal for flower maturation and pollination. The skunk cabbage is, then, a &ldquowarm-blooded&rdquo plant!

Pollination
The warm micro-environment inside the spathe along with the foul odors produced by the spadix flowers (odors reminiscent of rotting meat or decaying carcasses&hellip.these odors are the obvious source of both the plants many common names and also its scientific species designation) attracts the earliest flies and hymenopterans of the forest ecosystem. These flying insects crawl into the opening of the spathe and move across the floral parts of spadix. These floral parts develop sequentially with the lower female (ovule producing) parts maturing first and the upper male (pollen producing) parts maturing only after the ovules have been pollinated. This sequencing prevents self-pollination and facilitates and sustains the intermixing of genetic material and the overall genetic diversity of a population.

Flower and Fruit
The flower forms a fruit head after pollination. The surrounding spathe withers away exposing the 2 inch or so diameter ball. This fruit head is often the same reddish to brownish purple color of the spathe. This is also the time when the green leaves of the plant unfurl around the central fruit head. In late summer these fruit heads crumble and deposit their berry-like fruits on the ground around the fading leaves of the plant. These berries may decompose in the wet soil or be eaten (by a number of species including wood ducks, ring-necked pheasants, ruffed grouse, and bobwhite quail). Only a very small number will germinate, either in the fall or in the next spring, to form new skunk cabbage plants.

Leaves
The leaves and stems of the skunk cabbage are quite fragile and lack substantial amounts of woody, supportive tissue. The leaves begin to decompose on the standing plant through the summer and are so insubstantial that they make very little persisting leaf litter around the central rhizome. The leaves when crushed emit the same foul odor as the flowers. These leaves are also rich in calcium oxalate crystals which are irritating and may even be toxic if ingested. Both the odors and the presence of the calcium oxalate crystals greatly inhibit herbivory on the skunk cabbage leaves. Some animals, though, (like black bears, Canadian geese, and ring-necked pheasants) have been observed consuming these leaves especially when the leaves are young and just unfurling in the spring.

Human Use
Skunk cabbage has been used in a variety of folk medicine traditions. Native Americans dried the leaves and used them to facilitate the healing of skin wounds. They also crushed the leaves and inhaled the vapors to relieve headaches. European settlers used the plant as a contraceptive agent ingesting small amounts of skunk cabbage leaves daily in the belief that the dosage would reduce fertility. In the 19th Century the United States Pharmacopeia listed the uses for skunk cabbage as treatments for asthma, epilepsy, coughs, and rheumatism.

/> This site is licensed under a Creative Commons License. View Terms of Use.


Cabbage: Its History, Uses And Culture

Cabbage has been in cultivation for thousands of years. The ancient Romans loved it and used it for several purposes. Cato advised eating cabbage soaked in vinegar before embarking upon an evening of heavy drinking and the accepted remedy for a Roman hangover was simply more cabbage. Caesar's armies carried cabbage with them and used it not only for food, but bound wounds with the leaves to reduce infection. Modern studies do show that cabbage has antibacterial properties and actually reduces inflammation.

Cabbage was introduced into Europe by the conquering Romans and there the plant was bred into the familiar form we recognize today. It was easily cultivated in the cooler parts of northern Europe and quickly became a popular food. It produced a large harvest in the short growing season and was a wonderful addition to the meager diet of the rural folk. The French word "caboche" literally means "head," so the English name "cabbage" is most likely an adaptation upon it. The Danish were probably the originators of what we know as coleslaw, as their word for cabbage is "kool," and their word for salad is "sla." So, "cabbage salad" would be "koolsla."

The explorers of the 17 th and 18 th centuries carried cabbage in their ship's stores for their crews to eat and the high Vitamin C content helped stave off the scurvy that was so common among sailors. By this time, a pickled form of the vegetable was popular in Europe and the French from the Alsace area gave it the name of "Choucroute"(sauerkraut). It has even been noted that on one of Captain Cook's voyages that sailors who were injured in a storm had their wounds bound with cabbage to help prevent gangrene.

This is a very humble vegetable, eaten by hungry peasants when very little else was available, but frowned upon by the higher classes who were suspicious of any vegetable. It was even rumored that it was among several fruits and vegetables were said to cause the Plague and were to be avoided at all costs. All the while, hungry Irish, Scandinavians, Germans and French lived upon cabbage, and little else.

Cabbage was a wonderful food for rich and poor alike, although a pot of cabbage boiling over the fire was more likely to be found in the more modest homes. It seems that the strong aroma was offending to the delicate, higher-class noses. The peasants had a highly nutritious food that was easy to grow and stored well.

A single serving of cabbage contains nearly half of the daily Vitamin C requirement and has significant levels of manganese, iron, and vitamin B6. Cabbage also is high in dietary fiber and low in calories, which makes it an ideal food for those watching their weight.

The best cabbage is grown in cool weather, in rich soil and has a steady source of moisture. Start seeds indoors 8 to 10 weeks before the planned set-out date. As cabbage plants can tolerate frost, it is usually one of the first plants to go in the garden. Just be sure to plant out after the last projected freeze date, as freezing temperatures can harm the young transplants.

Cabbage plants consist of more than just the round green or purple balls that one sees in the supermarkets. When it is growing, there is a large rosette of leaves that surround the central head. Each variety is different in the it's space requirements, but 12" to 18" is a minimum distance between plants. Set the rows two or three feet apart so that there will be room for cultivation.

Cutworms like cabbage plants, so it's advisable to place a collar of some sort around the young transplants. A paper cup with the bottom cut out is good as it will simply decompose. Other pests include cabbage looper caterpillars and flea beetles. The cabbage loopers are a green caterpillar with thin white stripes. They have no legs in the center part of their bodies, so they move with an "inchworm like" motion. They tend to like the undersides of the leaves so may be difficult to spot. If treating with an insecticide, be sure to spray the undersides of the leaves. Flea beetle damage looks like the plant has been hit with buckshot. Tiny round holes appear and flea beetles can eat a new planting of cabbage to the ground almost overnight if left unchecked. Covering the plants with row covers and spraying with a neem oil product will help control them. Planting a more desirable food such as Chinese Giant Mustard will distract the flea beetles from the cabbage.

Cabbage can be harvested at any point after the heads form. They tend to split if left in the field after heavy rains, so be aware of the weather conditions as they mature. Remove the cut stems, leaves and roots and compost them to keep down pest populations. Cabbage can be stored in a cool dark place such as a root cellar.

Many countries and cultures enjoy some form of cabbage prepared in a great number of ways. Sauerkraut and coleslaw from Europe and colcannon from Ireland. The Hungarians have their stuffed cabbage and the Koreans love their kimchi. Cabbage is a staple among cultures the world over.

The following is a Norwegian recipe for cooked cabbage that is similar to a hot sauerkraut. It is known as Surkål, (sour cabbage) and is commonly eaten with fatty meats such as pork. Being flavored with caraway, it is said that it helps with digestion.

Norwegian Style Sauerkraut. (Surkål)

1 ½ pounds of cabbage -green or red

1 or 2 apples

2 tsp salt 1 tsp caraway seeds

Shred the cabbage into strips about ¼" wide

Place cabbage, apples and seasonings in pan

Pour water over. If red cabbage is used, be sure to add vinegar at the start of cooking to retain the bright color.

Simmer covered for 30-45 minutes until cabbage is tender. Adding a bit of water if necessary to prevent sticking.

The dish should have a tangy sweet/sour taste.

Enjoy cabbage. It's tasty, good for you and won't make you fat!

About Melody Rose

About Melody Rose

I come from a long line of Kentuckians who love the Good Earth. I love to learn about every living thing, and love to share what I've learned. Photography is one of my passions, and all of the images in my articles are my own, except where credited.


Ministry of Agriculture, Food and Rural Affairs

Onion thrips, Thrips tabaci (Lindeman), is a regular and potentially serious pest of onions and cabbage in Ontario. Thrips are widely distributed in Canada and the United States and feed on a variety of vegetables, field crops and weed species. Thrips first appear in most vegetable fields in mid-to-late June and have several overlapping generations throughout the summer months.

Description

Thrips are small, slender and fast-moving. The adults are approximately 2 mm in length, pale yellow to brown in colour and pointed at both ends (Figure 1). The male of the species is wingless and is rarely found. The females have four very slender wings fringed with close-set long hairs. When at rest, the wings are laid over the abdomen and extend slightly past it. The nymphs are similar in shape but smaller in size and pale yellow in colour.

Figure 1 . Adult thrips feeding on cabbage.

Biology

In Ontario, both adults and nymphs overwinter on winter grains, clover or alfalfa. Migration to vegetable crops usually occurs in early summer when winter grains begin to dry down. Once in an onion or cabbage field, the thrips seek cover between or under leaves, where they begin to feed. The females insert white, bean-shaped eggs into the leaf tissue. The eggs hatch in 5 to 10 days. The nymphs grow in size and pass through four distinct stages, the last two of which are spent in the soil. Development form egg to adult requires from 10 to 30 days, depending on temperature. Once mature, females soon begin to lay eggs. The females are able to reproduce without mating and, therefore, are not dependent on the presence of males of the species. Consequently, increases in the thrips population can occur very rapidly, especially during periods of hot, dry weather. Eggs, nymphs and adults may be found together at any time during the summer and produce many overlapping generations.

Damage

Onions

Damage is caused by both nymph and adult feeding. Thrips use their rasping and sucking mouthparts to scrape the leaf surface and suck up the exuding plant juices. This feeding produces silvery-white, mottled lesions on the leaf surface (Figure 2). Initially, injury is difficult to detect, due to the concealed location of the thrips. A close look between the leaf sheaths is necessary to locate active thrips or leaf injury. Large numbers of thrips can cause serious damage to onions. The lesions may become so numerous that the entire plant takes on a white or straw-coloured appearance. Continued feeding results in leaf distortion, followed by wilting, browning and premature lodging.

Figure 2 . Thrips damage on onions. Note the silvery-white lesions.

During hot, dry seasons, damage from thrips becomes most serious and may result in reduced onion yields. Feeding also puts added stress on the plant, making the onion more susceptible to bacterial rot and fungal attack.

Cabbage

Figure 3. Thrips damage on cabbage appears as small brownish-gray wartlike growths on the leaf surface.

In Ontario, injury to cabbage by thrips is usually most serious in storage cabbage or heads harvested in late summer and early fall. Feeding by thrips results in a proliferation of cells protruding from the injured epidermal layer of the head. The result is small, brownish-gray water-like growths on the leaf surface (Figure 3). The wrapper leaves may also show silver coloured mottled lesions along with black fecal material. Feeding by thrips represents more of a cosmetic problem than a loss in yield. If feeding injury is severe or several thrips are present on the cabbage, heads may be unacceptable for the fresh and processing market. Some varieties with tighter heads are less susceptible to injury and should be considered if thrips become a perennial problem.

Monitoring and Control

Onions

Yellow sticky board traps used for monitoring the onion maggot can also be used to detect the migration of thrips from their overwintering hosts.

Once the migration has begun, individual onion plants in several sections of the field should be inspected on a regular basis. To find thrips, the leaves must be parted to reveal the youngest emerging leaf in the centre of the plant (Figure 4). Thrips prefer this area because it is the most succulent part of the plant and provides excellent protection from weather and insecticides. Adult thrips may also be found on older leaves, particularly where leaves have folded over, providing a sheltered area. Areas where thrips are most likely to be found are the field borders, near woods or in the vicinity of grain or field crops. Then examining the plants, look for injury as well as for the presence of the insects.

Figure 4 . Separating the leaves of onion reveals both damage and active thrips.

At least 50 plants should be examined when scouting for thrips in addition it is necessary to estimate the average leaf stage of the crop prior to plant sampling. Carefully record the approximate number of thrips per plant that you find. Then divide this total by the average leaf stage of the crop to give you a "thrips per leaf" estimate. Threshold guidelines are as follows: 3 thrips per leaf for cooking onions, 1 thrip per leaf for Spanish onions and green bunching onions". Spanish onions have a lower tolerance because they are very susceptible to bacterial diseases which thrip's damage can enhance. Green onions also have a lower tolerance because the tops are sold and must be free of blemishes.

Cabbage

Sticky board traps are useful to determine the time that populations of thrips are migrating into the crop. Traps should be located along the outer edges of the field and examined twice weekly. Once an influx of thrips has been detected, scouting should become more intense. Scouting for thrips can be integrated with scouting for lepidopterous larvae (caterpillars). Twenty to thirty plants should be examined two times a week with emphasis on plants around the borders of the field. Thrips are normally found on the underside of the leaf or within the leaves of the developing head. They are often difficult to find, making it important to also look for signs of feeding. After head formation, damage can be detected by peeling off the outermost leaves. Pesticide applications, if necessary, are more effective prior to head formation. Thorough insecticide coverage is essential for good control of thrips. Due to the behavior of the insect, sprays should be directed at both the top and underside of the leaves. Once thrips are between the leaves in a head, they are difficult to contact with an insecticide.

Thrips have many natural enemies which include ladybird beetles, minute pirate bugs, lacewings, spiders and predacious and parasitic wasps. The fungus Entomopthora thripidum also infects thrips providing some natural control. In a season with low insect pressure, these natural control measures can prevent thrips from causing economic losses. Heavy rains will also reduce thrip numbers by washing them from the plants. Reduction in thrip numbers has also been observed with the use of overhead irrigation.


Interactions ?

Moderate Interaction

Be cautious with this combination

Acetaminophen (Tylenol, others) interacts with CABBAGE

The body breaks down acetaminophen (Tylenol, others) to a get rid of it. Cabbage might increase the breakdown of acetaminophen (Tylenol, others). Taking cabbage along with acetaminophen (Tylenol, others) might decrease the effectiveness of acetaminophen (Tylenol, others).

Medications changed by the liver (Cytochrome P450 1A2 (CYP1A2) substrates) interacts with CABBAGE

Some medications are changed and broken down by the liver.

Cabbage might increase how quickly the liver breaks down some medications. Taking cabbage along with some medications that are changed by the liver can decrease the effectiveness of some medications. Before taking cabbage talk to your healthcare provider if you take any medications that are changed by the liver.

Some of these medications that are changed by the liver include clozapine (Clozaril), cyclobenzaprine (Flexeril), fluvoxamine (Luvox), haloperidol (Haldol), imipramine (Tofranil), mexiletine (Mexitil), olanzapine (Zyprexa), pentazocine (Talwin), propranolol (Inderal), tacrine (Cognex), theophylline, zileuton (Zyflo), zolmitriptan (Zomig), and others.

Medications changed by the liver (Glucuronidated Drugs) interacts with CABBAGE

The liver helps the body break down and change some medications. The body breaks down some medications to get rid of them. Cabbage might increase how quickly the body breaks down some medications changed by the liver. Taking cabbage along with these medications changed by the liver might decrease the effectiveness of some medications change by the liver.

Some of these medications changed by the liver include acetaminophen, atorvastatin (Lipitor), diazepam (Valium), digoxin, entacapone (Comtan), estrogen, irinotecan (Camptosar), lamotrigine (Lamictal), lorazepam (Ativan), lovastatin (Mevacor), meprobamate, morphine, oxazepam (Serax), and others.

Oxazepam (Serax) interacts with CABBAGE

The body breaks down oxazepam (Serax) to get rid of it. Cabbage can increase how quickly the body gets rid of oxazepam (Serax). Taking cabbage along with oxazepam (Serax) might decrease the effectiveness of oxazepam (Serax).

Warfarin (Coumadin) interacts with CABBAGE

Cabbage contains large amounts of vitamin K. Vitamin K is used by the body to help blood clot. Warfarin (Coumadin) is used to slow blood clotting. By helping the blood clot, cabbage might decrease the effectiveness of warfarin (Coumadin). Be sure to have your blood checked regularly. The dose of your warfarin (Coumadin) might need to be changed.


25 thoughts on &ldquo Cabbage Anyone?? &rdquo

We make cabbage burgers. They’re tasty and freezable. I bet even the little ones would like them. They were a school lunch that was widely liked. Let me know if you want a recipe.

It may be a good year for homemade sauerkraut. My uncle made it one year and I have a hard time enjoying store bought now.

We love egg rolls. Cut up the cabbage (1 small- med head), add bean sprouts, water chestnuts and bamboo shoots cut up. Put soy sauce over this with Chinese 5 spice and stir often. Leave overnight. I usually fill the bigger Tupperware bowl. (They now make one larger). Fill wrappers with mixture draining liquid off. Deep fry and enjoy. This usually makes 3 pig of wrappers ( 45) they freeze well but are not crispy when microwaved. Look for recipes as my family likes only this. I make a homemade sweet and sour sauce too.

When we moved back from. California. We planted a garden the cabbage was mehh just like yours is asked a neighbor who had lived here all her life about how she started cabbage. She told me to burn some wood etc. In a space in the garden on February 2nd. And when the ashes had cooled sprinkle the cabbage seeds and let them alone. We did the cabbages sprouted and never got frost bitten even though we had several severe freezes. They also stored the whole following winter until used up.
I have baked ham and cabbage together. It was delicious.

Never heard of a cabbage burger here in Australia but I would love to know how to make then, sounds like they could be very keto friendly. Thanks, Marie in Western Australia

When we moved back from. California. We planted a garden the cabbage was mehh just like yours is asked a neighbor who had lived here all her life about how she started cabbage. She told me to burn some wood etc. In a space in the garden on February 2nd. And when the ashes had cooled sprinkle the cabbage seeds and let them alone. We did the cabbages sprouted and never got frost bitten even though we had several severe freezes. They also stored the whole following winter until used up.
I have baked ham and cabbage together. It was delicious.

My family always has kapusta at big gatherings. It’s cabbage with bacon or salt pork, onion, celery, beans (I use pinto) and some sauerkraut mixed in. Some add kielbasa or pork roast, too. It’s a love it or hate it dish but always there to honor our heritage.

We have a family favorite i made when my kids were little and now they all make it at their homes. It is a cabbage, onion, sausage and sour cream mixture that is then served in pita bread. Very yummy!

I love cabbage. Never heard of cabbage burgers but I’d like to try them and I’ll bet they are tasty. Nothing better than cabbage grown in your own garden That is a story that you and Kalissa won’t ever forget!

I like cabbage sliced in 1 inch rounds and fried. Add some vinegar, a tiny bit of sugar, and some cooked bacon on top….. Heavenly

Love cabbage. Can use it many ways & makes house smell so delicious cooking in soup. It’s especially nice if you live a ways from a grocery store because it keeps much better than lettuce. I hope you can find room for all these plants in your garden then share the excess like I’ve done.

My mother fried cabbage. onions with cheese and potato pierogis and served with sour cream. It was delicious. My husband won’t eat it.

I made up my own recipe using a package of coleslaw and Italian sausage. I brown the sausage, if there is a lot of fat I take most of it off, Then I put the whole bag of coleslaw in with the sausage, a little bit of water and cook it until the coleslaw is cook. I will add some soy sauce. I like it and have to eat it for a about 3 days because it makes a goodly amount. I am single so I am the only one eating it!! I fix some brown rice to eat with it. I think you could use just cut up cabbage instead of the slaw.

Whoops!! Off to check out that bacon cabbage recipe…

These cabbage recipe ideas couldn’t have come at a better time, having spent yesterday cutting and blanching 9 cabbages (planted last autumn) for the freezer, and there are still 5 left in the veg garden! Thanks Jo and your readers :)

I love fried cabbage–yup–just shredded cabbage fried in olive oil with plenty of black pepper–I let mine get medium crispy–LOVE at first bite!! Hugs, Julierose:)))

There was this one time when I was a teen–decades ago and obviously before cell phones–that Mom and I separated ways in a small city, with plans to meet up a while later at a certain time and place. We each waited for the other IN DIFFERENT STORES for an hour. I don’t remember how we got back together, but we finally did.
Communication breakdowns happen, for sure!! Might as well laugh as cry!

Ha! My husband did that to me with tomato plants, only he got me two flats of 48 plants! I gave away what I could, but ended up with nearly 80 tomato plants. I got as many into containers as I could (don’t have a great garden plot yet), then planted the rest in our not very good clay-ey soil, telling them to Go with God. Good thing I like canning tomato sauce! And yes, you should definitely try making homemade sauerkraut–there’s nothing like it.

Cabbage soup… diced cabbage ( doesn’t hang off the spoon), chicken stock, sugar, onion, garlic ( diced from a jar),grated nutmeg, seasonings of choice, 1 lg., can of diced/ crished or . tomatoes, cook till cabbage is tender, add “coined” kielbasa , check seasoning, ENJOY. even my late husband ate with chunks of garlic bread. Since we both enjoyed garlic, we enjoyed a kiss good night!

My husband & I loved the Cabbage soup that we use to eat at Shoney’s so my daughter came up this recipe that we love: 1-46oz. can of V-8 juice, 1# hamburger browned, 1 can of beef broth, 1-28oz. can of tomatoes, 1can of rotel tomatoes, 1 onion chopped, 1 head of cabbage chopped. Combine & cook for about half hour or until cabbage is cooked.

My fav chicken salad uses fresh cabbage— look up Oriental chicken salad.

I add chopped cabbage to vegetable soup and make a casserole that I call unstuffed cabbage rolls. It has all the ingredients of cabbage rolls but in casserole form. My mom always made something that she just called boiled dinner that had ham hocks, cabbage, and potatoes all boiled together. Other than cole slaw, that’s about the extent of cabbage things I like. I detest sauerkraut and only make it on New Year’s Day for my family to keep my late mother-in-law’s tradition going.

My two family favorite cabbage recipes are:
1) Eggroll in a bowl: https://stylishcravings.com/low-carb-easy-make-egg-roll-bowl/. (Actually, I bake these inside eggroll wrappers – 15 minutes at 400F) The most exotic ingredient is the egg roll wrapper, and that’s optional.
2) something we call science class slaw. It’s a bit of an Asian flair dressing: 1 part rice vinegar, 1 part soy sauce, 1 part oil (I usually use a combo of olive/vegetable oil and toasted sesame oil). It looks prettier with black sesame seeds sprinkled on top (but regular toasted ones or none work too).

Leave a Reply Cancel reply

Subscribe to Blog via Email

Help support this blog by doing your shopping using the link below. Commissions from your purchases help keep this content free. Thanks!


Health Benefits of Kohlrabi

Kohlrabi may look funny and have a silly-sounding name, but it offers serious potential health benefits! With a mild flavor and crisp texture, it’s easy to add to many dishes. And it’s also quite simple to grow! Read on to learn more about kohlrabi’s nutritional value and why you should add this vegetable to your diet.


Appearance

It is useful to know what both the larva and the butterfly look like because seeing either near your plants most likely means that you'll start seeing damage to your brassicas (such as cabbage, broccoli, and kale.) The cabbage white butterfly has off-white wings, with one or two grayish-black spots per wing. The wingspan is roughly 2 inches across. The larva (the worm that does the actual damage) is a velvety green, inchworm-type caterpillar that is roughly 1 inch long. The eggs of the larvae are found on the undersides of leaves and are yellow and oval-shaped.  


Now we need to weigh the cabbage so that it will remain underneath the brine. I prefer to use a celery stick for this purpose as it is quite flexible to be tucked under the neck of the jar.

Estimate the size of the celery stick needed.

Cut one, check if you guessed right. Try to place it under the neck of the jar so that it holds the cabbage down. Adjust the size if necessary.

You may have to cut 2 or 3 pieces altogether. Place them into the jar as shown in the photos.


The Biological Basis of Morality

Do we invent our moral absolutes in order to make society workable? Or are these enduring principles expressed to us by some transcendent or Godlike authority? Efforts to resolve this conundrum have perplexed, sometimes inflamed, our best minds for centuries, but the natural sciences are telling us more and more about the choices we make and our reasons for making them

CENTURIES of debate on the origin of ethics come down to this: Either ethical principles, such as justice and human rights, are independent of human experience, or they are human inventions. The distinction is more than an exercise for academic philosophers. The choice between these two understandings makes all the difference in the way we view ourselves as a species. It measures the authority of religion, and it determines the conduct of moral reasoning.

The two assumptions in competition are like islands in a sea of chaos, as different as life and death, matter and the void. One cannot learn which is correct by pure logic the answer will eventually be reached through an accumulation of objective evidence. Moral reasoning, I believe, is at every level intrinsically consilient with -- compatible with, intertwined with -- the natural sciences. (I use a form of the word "consilience" -- literally a "jumping together" of knowledge as a result of the linking of facts and fact-based theory across disciplines to create a common groundwork of explanation -- because its rarity has preserved its precision.)

Every thoughtful person has an opinion on which premise is correct. But the split is not, as popularly supposed, between religious believers and secularists. It is between transcendentalists, who think that moral guidelines exist outside the human mind, and empiricists, who think them contrivances of the mind. In simplest terms, the options are as follows: I believe in the independence of moral values, whether from God or not, and I believe that moral values come from human beings alone, whether or not God exists.

Theologians and philosophers have almost always focused on transcendentalism as the means to validate ethics. They seek the grail of natural law, which comprises freestanding principles of moral conduct immune to doubt and compromise. Christian theologians, following Saint Thomas Aquinas's reasoning in Summa Theologiae, by and large consider natural law to be an expression of God's will. In this view, human beings have an obligation to discover the law by diligent reasoning and to weave it into the routine of their daily lives. Secular philosophers of a transcendental bent may seem to be radically different from theologians, but they are actually quite similar, at least in moral reasoning. They tend to view natural law as a set of principles so powerful, whatever their origin, as to be self-evident to any rational person. In short, transcendental views are fundamentally the same whether God is invoked or not.

For example, when Thomas Jefferson, following John Locke, derived the doctrine of natural rights from natural law, he was more concerned with the power of transcendental statements than with their origin, divine or secular. In the Declaration of Independence he blended secular and religious presumptions in one transcendentalist sentence, thus deftly covering all bets: "We hold these Truths to be self-evident, that all Men are created equal, that they are endowed by their Creator with certain unalienable Rights, that among these are Life, Liberty, and the Pursuit of Happiness." That assertion became the cardinal premise of America's civil religion, the righteous sword wielded by Abraham Lincoln and Martin Luther King Jr., and it endures as the central ethic binding together the diverse peoples of the United States.

So compelling are such fruits of natural-law theory, especially when the Deity is also invoked, that they may seem to place the transcendentalist assumption beyond question. But to its noble successes must be added appalling failures. It has been perverted many times in the past -- used, for example, to argue passionately for colonial conquest, slavery, and genocide. Nor was any great war ever fought without each side thinking its cause transcendentally sacred in some manner or other.

So perhaps we need to take empiricism more seriously. In the empiricist view, ethics is conduct favored consistently enough throughout a society to be expressed as a code of principles. It reaches its precise form in each culture according to historical circumstance. The codes, whether adjudged good or evil by outsiders, play an important role in determining which cultures flourish and which decline.

The crux of the empiricist view is its emphasis on objective knowledge. Because the success of an ethical code depends on how wisely it interprets moral sentiments, those who frame one should know how the brain works, and how the mind develops. The success of ethics also depends on how accurately a society can predict the consequences of particular actions as opposed to others, especially in cases of moral ambiguity.

The empiricist argument holds that if we explore the biological roots of moral behavior, and explain their material origins and biases, we should be able to fashion a wise and enduring ethical consensus. The current expansion of scientific inquiry into the deeper processes of human thought makes this venture feasible.

The choice between transcendentalism and empiricism will be the coming century's version of the struggle for men's souls. Moral reasoning will either remain centered in idioms of theology and philosophy, where it is now, or shift toward science-based material analysis. Where it settles will depend on which world view is proved correct, or at least which is more widely perceived to be correct.

Ethicists, scholars who specialize in moral reasoning, tend not to declare themselves on the foundations of ethics, or to admit fallibility. Rarely do we see an argument that opens with the simple statement This is my starting point, and it could be wrong. Ethicists instead favor a fretful passage from the particular to the ambiguous, or the reverse -- vagueness into hard cases. I suspect that almost all are transcendentalists at heart, but they rarely say so in simple declarative sentences. One cannot blame them very much explaining the ineffable is difficult.

I am an empiricist. On religion I lean toward deism, but consider its proof largely a problem in astrophysics. The existence of a God who created the universe (as envisioned by deism) is possible, and the question may eventually be settled, perhaps by forms of material evidence not yet imagined. Or the matter may be forever beyond human reach. In contrast, and of far greater importance to humanity, the idea of a biological God, one who directs organic evolution and intervenes in human affairs (as envisioned by theism), is increasingly contravened by biology and the brain sciences.

The same evidence, I believe, favors a purely material origin of ethics, and it meets the criterion of consilience: causal explanations of brain activity and evolution, while imperfect, already cover most facts known about behavior we term "moral." Although this conception is relativistic (in other words, dependent on personal viewpoint), it can, if evolved carefully, lead more directly and safely to stable moral codes than can transcendentalism, which is also, when one thinks about it, ultimately relativistic.

Of course, lest I forget, I may be wrong.

THE argument of the empiricist has roots that go back to Aristotle's Nicomachean Ethics and, in the beginning of the modern era, to David Hume's A Treatise of Human Nature (1739-1740). The first clear evolutionary elaboration of it was by Charles Darwin, in The Descent of Man (1871).

Again, religious transcendentalism is bolstered by secular transcendentalism, to which it is fundamentally similar. Immanuel Kant, judged by history the greatest of secular philosophers, addressed moral reasoning very much as a theologian. Human beings, he argued, are independent moral agents with a wholly free will, capable of obeying or breaking moral law: "There is in man a power of self-determination, independent of any coercion through sensuous impulses." Our minds are subject to a categorical imperative, Kant said, of what our actions ought to be. The imperative is a good in itself alone, apart from all other considerations, and it can be recognized by this rule: "Act only on that maxim you wish will become a universal law." Most important, and transcendental, ought has no place in nature. Nature, Kant said, is a system of cause and effect, whereas moral choice is a matter of free will, absent cause and effect. In making moral choices, in rising above mere instinct, human beings transcend the realm of nature and enter a realm of freedom that belongs exclusively to them as rational creatures.

Now, this formulation has a comforting feel to it, but it makes no sense at all in terms of either material or imaginable entities, which is why Kant, even apart from his tortured prose, is so hard to understand. Sometimes a concept is baffling not because it is profound but because it is wrong. This idea does not accord, we know now, with the evidence of how the brain works.

In Principia Ethica (1903), G. E. Moore, the founder of modern ethical philosophy, essentially agreed with Kant. In his view, moral reasoning cannot dip into psychology and the social sciences in order to locate ethical principles, because those disciplines yield only a causal picture and fail to illuminate the basis of moral justification. So to reach the normative ought by way of the factual is is to commit a basic error of logic, which Moore called the naturalistic fallacy. John Rawls, in A Theory of Justice (1971), once again traveled the transcendental road. He offered the very plausible suggestion that justice be defined as fairness, which is to be accepted as an intrinsic good. It is the imperative we would follow if we had no starting information about our own future status in life. But in making such a suggestion Rawls ventured no thought on where the human brain comes from or how it works. He offered no evidence that justice-as-fairness is consistent with human nature, hence practicable as a blanket premise. Probably it is, but how can we know except by blind trial and error?

Had Kant, Moore, and Rawls known modern biology and experimental psychology, they might well not have reasoned as they did. Yet as this century closes, transcendentalism remains firm in the hearts not just of religious believers but also of countless scholars in the social sciences and the humanities who, like Moore and Rawls, have chosen to insulate their thinking from the natural sciences.

Many philosophers will respond by saying, Ethicists don't need that kind of information. You really can't pass from is to ought. You can't describe a genetic predisposition and suppose that because it is part of human nature, it is somehow transformed into an ethical precept. We must put moral reasoning in a special category, and use transcendental guidelines as required.

No, we do not have to put moral reasoning in a special category and use transcendental premises, because the posing of the naturalistic fallacy is itself a fallacy. For if ought is not is, what is? To translate is into ought makes sense if we attend to the objective meaning of ethical precepts. They are very unlikely to be ethereal messages awaiting revelation, or independent truths vibrating in a nonmaterial dimension of the mind. They are more likely to be products of the brain and the culture. From the consilient perspective of the natural sciences, they are no more than principles of the social contract hardened into rules and dictates -- the behavioral codes that members of a society fervently wish others to follow and are themselves willing to accept for the common good. Precepts are the extreme on a scale of agreements that range from casual assent, to public sentiment, to law, to that part of the canon considered sacred and unalterable. The scale applied to adultery might read as follows:

In transcendental thinking, the chain of causation runs downward from the given ought in religion or natural law through jurisprudence to education and finally to individual choice. The argument from transcendentalism takes the following general form: The order of nature contains supreme principles, either divine or intrinsic, and we will be wise to learn about them and find the means to conform to them. Thus John Rawls opens A Theory of Justice with a proposition he regards as irrevocable: "In a just society the liberties of equal citizenship are taken as settled the rights secured by justice are not subject to political bargaining or to the calculus of social interests." As many critiques have made clear, that premise can lead to unhappy consequences when applied to the real world, including a tightening of social control and a decline in personal initiative. A very different premise, therefore, is suggested by Robert Nozick in Anarchy, State, and Utopia (1974): "Individuals have rights, and there are things no person or group may do to them (without violating their rights). So strong and far-reaching are these rights that they raise the question of what, if anything, the state and its officials may do." Rawls would point us toward egalitarianism regulated by the state, Nozick toward libertarianism in a minimalist state.

The empiricist view, in contrast, searching for an origin of ethical reasoning that can be objectively studied, reverses the chain of causation. The individual is seen as predisposed biologically to make certain choices. Through cultural evolution some of the choices are hardened into precepts, then into laws, and, if the predisposition or coercion is strong enough, into a belief in the command of God or the natural order of the universe. The general empiricist principle takes this form: Strong innate feeling and historical experience cause certain actions to be preferred we have experienced them, and have weighed their consequences, and agree to conform with codes that express them. Let us take an oath upon the codes, invest our personal honor in them, and suffer punishment for their violation. The empiricist view concedes that moral codes are devised to conform to some drives of human nature and to suppress others. Ought is the translation not of human nature but of the public will, which can be made increasingly wise and stable through an understanding of the needs and pitfalls of human nature. The empiricist view recognizes that the strength of commitment can wane as a result of new knowledge and experience, with the result that certain rules may be desacralized, old laws rescinded, and formerly prohibited behavior set free. It also recognizes that for the same reason new moral codes may need to be devised, with the potential of being made sacred in time.

IF the empiricist world view is correct, ought is just shorthand for one kind of factual statement, a word that denotes what society first chose (or was coerced) to do, and then codified. The naturalistic fallacy is thereby reduced to the naturalistic problem. The solution of the problem is not difficult: ought is the product of a material process. The solution points the way to an objective grasp of the origin of ethics.

A few investigators are now embarked on just such a foundational inquiry. Most agree that ethical codes have arisen by evolution through the interplay of biology and culture. In a sense these investigators are reviving the idea of moral sentiments that was developed in the eighteenth century by the British empiricists Francis Hutcheson, David Hume, and Adam Smith.

What have been thought of as moral sentiments are now taken to mean moral instincts (as defined by the modern behavioral sciences), subject to judgment according to their consequences. Such sentiments are thus derived from epigenetic rules -- hereditary biases in mental development, usually conditioned by emotion, that influence concepts and decisions made from them. The primary origin of moral instincts is the dynamic relation between cooperation and defection. The essential ingredient for the molding of the instincts during genetic evolution in any species is intelligence high enough to judge and manipulate the tension generated by the dynamism. That level of intelligence allows the building of complex mental scenarios well into the future. It occurs, so far as is known, only in human beings and perhaps their closest relatives among the higher apes.

A way of envisioning the hypothetical earliest stages of moral evolution is provided by game theory, particularly the solutions to the famous Prisoner's Dilemma. Consider the following typical scenario of the dilemma. Two gang members have been arrested for murder and are being questioned separately. The evidence against them is strong but not irrefutable. The first gang member believes that if he turns state's witness, he will be granted immunity and his partner will be sentenced to life in prison. But he is also aware that his partner has the same option, and that if both of them exercise it, neither will be granted immunity. That is the dilemma. Will the two gang members independently defect, so that both take the hard fall? They will not, because they agreed in advance to remain silent if caught. By doing so, both hope to be convicted on a lesser charge or escape punishment altogether. Criminal gangs have turned this principle of calculation into an ethical precept: Never rat on another member always be a stand-up guy. Honor does exist among thieves. The gang is a society of sorts its code is the same as that of a captive soldier in wartime, obliged to give only name, rank, and serial number.

In one form or another, comparable dilemmas that are solvable by cooperation occur constantly and everywhere in daily life. The payoff is variously money, status, power, sex, access, comfort, or health. Most of these proximate rewards are converted into the universal bottom line of Darwinian genetic fitness: greater longevity and a secure, growing family.

And so it has most likely always been. Imagine a Paleolithic band of five hunters. One considers breaking away from the others to look for an antelope on his own. If successful, he will gain a large quantity of meat and hide -- five times as much as if he stays with the band and they are successful. But he knows from experience that his chances of success are very low, much less than the chances of the band of five working together. In addition, whether successful alone or not, he will suffer animosity from the others for lessening their prospects. By custom the band members remain together and share equitably the animals they kill. So the hunter stays. He also observes good manners in doing so, especially if he is the one who makes the kill. Boastful pride is condemned, because it rips the delicate web of reciprocity.

Now suppose that human propensities to cooperate or defect are heritable: some people are innately more cooperative, others less so. In this respect moral aptitude would simply be like almost all other mental traits studied to date. Among traits with documented heritability, those closest to moral aptitude are empathy with the distress of others and certain processes of attachment between infants and their caregivers. To the heritability of moral aptitude add the abundant evidence of history that cooperative individuals generally survive longer and leave more offspring. Following that reasoning, in the course of evolutionary history genes predisposing people toward cooperative behavior would have come to predominate in the human population as a whole.

Such a process repeated through thousands of generations inevitably gave rise to moral sentiments. With the exception of psychopaths (if any truly exist), every person vividly experiences these instincts variously as conscience, self-respect, remorse, empathy, shame, humility, and moral outrage. They bias cultural evolution toward the conventions that express the universal moral codes of honor, patriotism, altruism, justice, compassion, mercy, and redemption.

The dark side of the inborn propensity to moral behavior is xenophobia. Because personal familiarity and common interest are vital in social transactions, moral sentiments evolved to be selective. People give trust to strangers with effort, and true compassion is a commodity in chronically short supply. Tribes cooperate only through carefully defined treaties and other conventions. They are quick to imagine themselves the victims of conspiracies by competing groups, and they are prone to dehumanize and murder their rivals during periods of severe conflict. They cement their own group loyalties by means of sacred symbols and ceremonies. Their mythologies are filled with epic victories over menacing enemies.

The complementary instincts of morality and tribalism are easily manipulated. Civilization has made them more so. Beginning about 10,000 years ago, a tick in geological time, when the agricultural revolution started in the Middle East, in China, and in Mesoamerica, populations increased tenfold in density over those of hunter-gatherer societies. Families settled on small plots of land, villages proliferated, and labor was finely divided as a growing minority of the populace specialized as craftsmen, traders, and soldiers. The rising agricultural societies became increasingly hierarchical. As chiefdoms and then states thrived on agricultural surpluses, hereditary rulers and priestly castes took power. The old ethical codes were transformed into coercive regulations, always to the advantage of the ruling classes. About this time the idea of law-giving gods originated. Their commands lent the ethical codes overpowering authority -- once again, no surprise, in the interests of the rulers.

Because of the technical difficulty of analyzing such phenomena in an objective manner, and because people resist biological explanations of their higher cortical functions in the first place, very little progress has been made in the biological exploration of the moral sentiments. Even so, it is astonishing that the study of ethics has advanced so little since the nineteenth century. The most distinguishing and vital qualities of the human species remain a blank space on the scientific map. I doubt that discussions of ethics should rest upon the freestanding assumptions of contemporary philosophers who have evidently never given thought to the evolutionary origin and material functioning of the human brain. In no other domain of the humanities is a union with the natural sciences more urgently needed.

When the ethical dimension of human nature is at last fully opened to such exploration, the innate epigenetic rules of moral reasoning will probably not prove to be aggregated into simple instincts such as bonding, cooperativeness, and altruism. Instead the rules will most probably turn out to be an ensemble of many algorithms, whose interlocking activities guide the mind across a landscape of nuanced moods and choices.

Such a prestructured mental world may at first seem too complicated to have been created by autonomous genetic evolution alone. But all the evidence of biology suggests that just this process was enough to spawn the millions of species of life surrounding us. Each kind of animal is furthermore guided through its life cycle by unique and often elaborate sets of instinctual algorithms, many of which are beginning to yield to genetic and neurobiological analyses. With all these examples before us, we may reasonably conclude that human behavior originated the same way.

MEANWHILE, the mélanges of moral reasoning employed by modern societies are, to put the matter simply, a mess. They are chimeras, composed of odd parts stuck together. Paleolithic egalitarian and tribalistic instincts are still firmly installed. As part of the genetic foundation of human nature, they cannot be replaced. In some cases, such as quick hostility to strangers and competing groups, they have become generally ill adapted and persistently dangerous. Above the fundamental instincts rise superstructures of arguments and rules that accommodate the novel institutions created by cultural evolution. These accommodations, which reflect the attempt to maintain order and further tribal interests, have been too volatile to track by genetic evolution they are not yet in the genes.

Little wonder, then, that ethics is the most publicly contested of all philosophical enterprises. Or that political science, which at its foundation is primarily the study of applied ethics, is so frequently problematic. Neither is informed by anything that would be recognizable as authentic theory in the natural sciences. Both ethics and political science lack a foundation of verifiable knowledge of human nature sufficient to produce cause-and-effect predictions and sound judgments based on them. Surely closer attention must be paid to the deep springs of ethical behavior. The greatest void in knowledge for such a venture is the biology of moral sentiments. In time this subject can be understood, I believe, by paying attention to the following topics:

* The definition of moral sentiments, first by precise descriptions from experimental psychology and then by analysis of the underlying neural and endocrine responses.

* The genetics of moral sentiments, most easily approached through measurements of the heritability of the psychological and physiological processes of ethical behavior, and eventually, with difficulty, through identification of the prescribing genes.

* The development of moral sentiments as products of the interactions of genes and the environment. Research is most effective when conducted at two levels: the histories of ethical systems as part of the emergence of different cultures, and the cognitive development of individuals living in a variety of cultures. Such investigations are already well along in anthropology and psychology. In the future they will be augmented by contributions from biology.

* The deep history of moral sentiments -- why they exist in the first place. Presumably they contributed to survival and reproductive success during the long periods of prehistoric time in which they genetically evolved.

From a convergence of these several approaches the true origin and meaning of ethical behavior may come into focus. If so, a more certain measure can then be taken of the strength and flexibility of the epigenetic rules composing the various moral sentiments. From that knowledge it should be possible to adapt ancient moral sentiments more wisely to the swiftly changing conditions of modern life into which, willy-nilly and largely in ignorance, we have plunged.

Then new answers might be found to the truly important questions of moral reasoning. How can the moral instincts be ranked? Which are best subdued and to what degree? Which should be validated by law and symbol? How can precepts be left open to appeal under extraordinary circumstances? In the new understanding can be located the most effective means for reaching consensus. No one can guess the exact form that agreements will take from one culture to the next. The process, however, can be predicted with assurance. It will be democratic, weakening the clash of rival religions and ideologies. History is moving decisively in that direction, and people are by nature too bright and too contentious to abide anything else. And the pace can be confidently predicted: change will come slowly, across generations, because old beliefs die hard, even when they are demonstrably false.

THE same reasoning that aligns ethical philosophy with science can also inform the study of religion. Religions are analogous to organisms. They have a life cycle. They are born, they grow, they compete, they reproduce, and, in the fullness of time, most die. In each of these phases religions reflect the human organisms that nourish them. They express a primary rule of human existence: Whatever is necessary to sustain life is also ultimately biological.

Successful religions typically begin as cults, which then increase in power and inclusiveness until they achieve tolerance outside the circle of believers. At the core of each religion is a creation myth, which explains how the world began and how the chosen people -- those subscribing to the belief system -- arrived at its center. Often a mystery, a set of secret instructions and formulas, is available to members who have worked their way to a higher state of enlightenment. The medieval Jewish cabala, the trigradal system of Freemasonry, and the carvings on Australian aboriginal spirit sticks are examples of such arcana. Power radiates from the center, gathering converts and binding followers to the group. Sacred places are designated, where the gods can be importuned, rites observed, and miracles witnessed.

The devotees of the religion compete as a tribe with those of other religions. They harshly resist the dismissal of their beliefs by rivals. They venerate self-sacrifice in defense of the religion.

The tribalistic roots of religion are similar to those of moral reasoning and may be identical. Religious rites, such as burial ceremonies, are very old. It appears that in the late Paleolithic period in Europe and the Middle East bodies were sometimes placed in shallow graves, accompanied by ocher or blossoms one can easily imagine such ceremonies performed to invoke spirits and gods. But, as theoretical deduction and the evidence suggest, the primitive elements of moral behavior are far older than Paleolithic ritual. Religion arose on a foundation of ethics, and it has probably always been used in one manner or another to justify moral codes.

The formidable influence of the religious drive is based on far more, however, than just the validation of morals. A great subterranean river of the mind, it gathers strength from a broad spread of tributary emotions. Foremost among them is the survival instinct. "Fear," as the Roman poet Lucretius said, "was the first thing on earth to make the gods." Our conscious minds hunger for a permanent existence. If we cannot have everlasting life of the body, then absorption into some immortal whole will serve. Anything will serve, as long as it gives the individual meaning and somehow stretches into eternity that swift passage of the mind and spirit lamented by Saint Augustine as the short day of time.

The understanding and control of life is another source of religious power. Doctrine draws on the same creative springs as science and the arts, its aim being the extraction of order from the mysteries and tumult of the material world. To explain the meaning of life it spins mythic narratives of the tribal history, populating the cosmos with protective spirits and gods. The existence of the supernatural, if accepted, testifies to the existence of that other world so desperately desired.

Religion is also mightily empowered by its principal ally, tribalism. The shamans and priests implore us, in somber cadence, Trust in the sacred rituals, become part of the immortal force, you are one of us. As your life unfolds, each step has mystic significance that we who love you will mark with a solemn rite of passage, the last to be performed when you enter that second world, free of pain and fear.

If the religious mythos did not exist in a culture, it would quickly be invented, and in fact it has been invented everywhere, thousands of times through history. Such inevitability is the mark of instinctual behavior in any species, which is guided toward certain states by emotion-driven rules of mental development. To call religion instinctive is not to suppose that any particular part of its mythos is untrue -- only that its sources run deeper than ordinary habit and are in fact hereditary, urged into existence through biases in mental development that are encoded in the genes.

Such biases are a predictable consequence of the brain's genetic evolution. The logic applies to religious behavior, with the added twist of tribalism. There is a hereditary selective advantage to membership in a powerful group united by devout belief and purpose. Even when individuals subordinate themselves and risk death in a common cause, their genes are more likely to be transmitted to the next generation than are those of competing groups who lack comparable resolve.

The mathematical models of population genetics suggest the following rule in the evolutionary origin of such altruism: If the reduction in survival and reproduction of individuals owing to genes for altruism is more than offset by the increased probability of survival of the group owing to the altruism, then altruism genes will rise in frequency throughout the entire population of competing groups. To put it as concisely as possible: the individual pays, his genes and tribe gain, altruism spreads.

LET me now suggest a still deeper significance of the empiricist theory of the origin of ethics and religion. If empiricism were disproved, and transcendentalism compellingly upheld, the discovery would be quite simply the most consequential in human history. That is the burden laid upon biology as it draws close to the humanities.

The matter is still far from resolved. But empiricism, as I have argued, is well supported thus far in the case of ethics. The objective evidence for or against it in religion is weaker, but at least still consistent with biology. For example, the emotions that accompany religious ecstasy clearly have a neurobiological source. At least one form of brain disorder is associated with hyperreligiosity, in which cosmic significance is given to almost everything, including trivial everyday events. One can imagine the biological construction of a mind with religious beliefs, although that alone would not disprove the logic of transcendentalism, or prove the beliefs themselves to be untrue.

Equally important, much if not all religious behavior could have arisen from evolution by natural selection. The theory fits -- crudely. The behavior includes at least some aspects of belief in gods. Propitiation and sacrifice, which are near-universals of religious practice, are acts of submission to a dominant being. They reflect one kind of dominance hierarchy, which is a general trait of organized mammalian societies. Like human beings, animals use elaborate signals to advertise and maintain their rank in the hierarchy. The details vary among species but also have consistent similarities across the board, as the following two examples will illustrate.

In packs of wolves the dominant animal walks erect and "proud," stiff-legged and deliberate, with head, tail, and ears up, and stares freely and casually at others. In the presence of rivals the dominant animal bristles its pelt while curling its lips to show teeth, and it takes first choice in food and space. A subordinate uses opposite signals. It turns away from the dominant individual while lowering its head, ears, and tail, and it keeps its fur sleek and its teeth covered. It grovels and slinks, and yields food and space when challenged.

In a troop of rhesus monkeys the alpha male is remarkably similar in mannerisms to a dominant wolf. He keeps his head and tail up, and walks in a deliberate, "regal" manner while casually staring at others. He climbs objects to maintain height above his rivals. When challenged he stares hard at the opponent with mouth open -- signaling aggression, not surprise -- and sometimes slaps the ground with open palms to signal his readiness to attack. The male or female subordinate affects a furtive walk, holding its head and tail down, turning away from the alpha and other higher-ranked individuals. It keeps its mouth shut except for a fear grimace, and when challenged makes a cringing retreat. It yields space and food and, in the case of males, estrous females.

My point is this: Behavioral scientists from another planet would notice immediately the parallels between animal dominance behavior on the one hand and human obeisance to religious and civil authority on the other. They would point out that the most elaborate rites of obeisance are directed at the gods, the hyperdominant if invisible members of the human group. And they would conclude, correctly, that in baseline social behavior, not just in anatomy, Homo sapiens has only recently diverged in evolution from a nonhuman primate stock.

Countless studies of animal species, whose instinctive behavior is unobscured by cultural elaboration, have shown that membership in dominance orders pays off in survival and lifetime reproductive success. That is true not just for the dominant individuals but for the subordinates as well. Membership in either class gives animals better protection against enemies and better access to food, shelter, and mates than does solitary existence. Furthermore, subordination in the group is not necessarily permanent. Dominant individuals weaken and die, and as a result some of the underlings advance in rank and appropriate more resources.

Modern human beings are unlikely to have erased the old mammalian genetic programs and devised other means of distributing power. All the evidence suggests that they have not. True to their primate heritage, people are easily seduced by confident, charismatic leaders, especially males. That predisposition is strong in religious organizations. Cults form around such leaders. Their power grows if they can persuasively claim special access to the supremely dominant, typically male figure of God. As cults evolve into religions, the image of the Supreme Being is reinforced by myth and liturgy. In time the authority of the founders and their successors is graven in sacred texts. Unruly subordinates, known as "blasphemers," are squashed.

The symbol-forming human mind, however, never remains satisfied with raw, apish feeling in any emotional realm. It strives to build cultures that are maximally rewarding in every dimension. Ritual and prayer permit religious believers to be in direct touch with the Supreme Being consolation from coreligionists softens otherwise unbearable grief the unexplainable is explained and an oceanic sense of communion with the larger whole is made possible.

Communion is the key, and hope rising from it is eternal out of the dark night of the soul arises the prospect of a spiritual journey to the light. For a special few the journey can be taken in this life. The mind reflects in certain ways in order to reach ever higher levels of enlightenment, until finally, when no further progress is possible, it enters a mystical union with the whole. Within the great religions such enlightenment is expressed by Hindu samadhi, Buddhist Zen satori, Sufi fana, and Pentecostal Christian rebirth. Something like it is also experienced by hallucinating preliterate shamans. What all these celebrants evidently feel (as I felt once, to some degree, as a reborn evangelical) is hard to put in words, but Willa Cather came as close as possible in a single sentence. In My Antonia her fictional narrator says, "That is happiness to be dissolved into something complete and great."

Of course that is happiness -- to find the godhead, or to enter the wholeness of nature, or otherwise to grasp and hold on to something ineffable, beautiful, and eternal. Millions seek it. They feel otherwise lost, adrift in a life without ultimate meaning. They enter established religions, succumb to cults, dabble in New Age nostrums. They push The Celestine Prophecy and other junk attempts at enlightenment onto the best-seller lists.

Perhaps, as I believe, these phenomena can all eventually be explained as functions of brain circuitry and deep genetic history. But this is not a subject that even the most hardened empiricist should presume to trivialize. The idea of mystical union is an authentic part of the human spirit. It has occupied humanity for millennia, and it raises questions of utmost seriousness for transcendentalists and scientists alike. What road, we ask, was traveled, what destination reached, by the mystics of history?

FOR many, the urge to believe in transcendental existence and immortality is overpowering. Transcendentalism, especially when reinforced by religious faith, is psychically full and rich it feels somehow right. By comparison, empiricism seems sterile and inadequate. In the quest for ultimate meaning the transcendentalist route is much easier to follow. That is why, even as empiricism is winning the mind, transcendentalism continues to win the heart. Science has always defeated religious dogma point by point when differences between the two were meticulously assessed. But to no avail. In the United States 16 million people belong to the Southern Baptist denomination, the largest favoring a literal interpretation of the Christian Bible, but the American Humanist Association, the leading organization devoted to secular and deistic humanism, has only 5,000 members.

Still, if history and science have taught us anything, it is that passion and desire are not the same as truth. The human mind evolved to believe in gods. It did not evolve to believe in biology. Acceptance of the supernatural conveyed a great advantage throughout prehistory, when the brain was evolving. Thus it is in sharp contrast to the science of biology, which was developed as a product of the modern age and is not underwritten by genetic algorithms. The uncomfortable truth is that the two beliefs are not factually compatible. As a result, those who hunger for both intellectual and religious truth face disquieting choices.

Meanwhile, theology tries to resolve the dilemma by evolving, sciencelike, toward abstraction. The gods of our ancestors were divine human beings. The Egyptians represented them as Egyptian (often with body parts of Nilotic animals), and the Greeks represented them as Greek. The great contribution of the Hebrews was to combine the entire pantheon into a single person, Yahweh (a patriarch appropriate to desert tribes), and to intellectualize his existence. No graven images were allowed. In the process, they rendered the divine presence less tangible. And so in biblical accounts it came to pass that no one, not even Moses approaching Yahweh in the burning bush, could look upon his face. In time the Jews were prohibited from even pronouncing his true full name. Nevertheless, the idea of a theistic God, omniscient, omnipotent, and closely involved in human affairs, has persisted to this day as the dominant religious image of Western culture.

During the Enlightenment a growing number of liberal Judeo-Christian theologians, wishing to accommodate theism to a more rationalist view of the material world, moved away from God as a literal person. Baruch Spinoza, the pre-eminent Jewish philosopher of the seventeenth century, visualized the deity as a transcendent substance present everywhere in the universe. Deus sive natura, "God or nature," he declared, they are interchangeable. For his philosophical pains he was banished from his synagogue under a comprehensive anathema, combining all the curses in the book. The risk of heresy notwithstanding, the depersonalization of God has continued steadily into the modern era. For Paul Tillich, one of the most influential Protestant theologians of the twentieth century, the assertion of the existence of God-as-person is not false it is just meaningless. Among many of the most liberal contemporary thinkers the denial of a concrete divinity takes the form of "process theology." Everything in this most extreme of ontologies is part of a seamless and endlessly complex web of unfolding relationships. God is manifest in everything.

Scientists, the roving scouts of the empiricist movement, are not immune to the idea of God. Those who favor it often lean toward some form of process theology. They ask this question: When the real world of space, time, and matter is well enough known, will that knowledge reveal the Creator's presence? Their hopes are vested in the theoretical physicists who pursue the final theory, the Theory of Everything, T.O.E., a system of interlocking equations that describe all that can be learned of the forces of the physical universe. T.O.E. is a "beautiful" theory, as Steven Weinberg has called it in his important book Dreams of a Final Theory -- beautiful because it will be elegant, expressing the possibility of unending complexity with minimal laws and symmetrical, because it will hold invariant through all space and time and inevitable, meaning that once it is stated, no part can be changed without invalidating the whole. All surviving subtheories can be fitted into it permanently, in the manner described by Einstein in his own contribution, the General Theory of Relativity. "The chief attraction of the theory," Einstein said, "lies in its logical completeness. If a single one of the conclusions drawn from it proves wrong, it must be given up to modify it without destroying the whole structure seems to be impossible."

The prospect of a final theory by the most mathematical of scientists might seem to signal the approach of a new religious awakening. Stephen Hawking, yielding to the temptation in A Brief History of Time (1988), declared that this scientific achievement "would be the ultimate triumph of human reason -- for then we would know the mind of God."

THE essence of humanity's spiritual dilemma is that we evolved genetically to accept one truth and discovered another. Can we find a way to erase the dilemma, to resolve the contradictions between the transcendentalist and empiricist world views?

Unfortunately, in my view, the answer is no. Furthermore, the choice between the two is unlikely to remain arbitrary forever. The assumptions underlying these world views are being tested with increasing severity by cumulative verifiable knowledge about how the universe works, from atom to brain to galaxy. In addition, the harsh lessons of history have taught us that one code of ethics is not always as good -- or at least not as durable -- as another. The same is true of religions. Some cosmologies are factually less correct than others, and some ethical precepts are less workable.

Human nature is biologically based, and it is relevant to ethics and religion. The evidence shows that because of its influence, people can readily be educated to only a narrow range of ethical precepts. They flourish within certain belief systems and wither in others. We need to know exactly why.

To that end I will be so presumptuous as to suggest how the conflict between the world views will most likely be settled. The idea of a genetic, evolutionary origin of moral and religious beliefs will continue to be tested by biological studies of complex human behavior. To the extent that the sensory and nervous systems appear to have evolved by natural selection, or at least some other purely material process, the empiricist interpretation will be supported. It will be further supported by verification of gene-culture coevolution, the essential process postulated by scientists to underlie human nature by linking changes in genes to changes in culture.

Now consider the alternative. To the extent that ethical and religious phenomena do not appear to have evolved in a manner congenial to biology, and especially to the extent that such complex behavior cannot be linked to physical events in the sensory and nervous systems, the empiricist position will have to be abandoned and a transcendentalist explanation accepted.

For centuries the writ of empiricism has been spreading into the ancient domain of transcendentalist belief, slowly at the start but quickening in the scientific age. The spirits our ancestors knew intimately fled first the rocks and trees and then the distant mountains. Now they are in the stars, where their final extinction is possible. But we cannot live without them. People need a sacred narrative. They must have a sense of larger purpose, in one form or another, however intellectualized. They will refuse to yield to the despair of animal mortality. They will continue to plead, in company with the psalmist, Now Lord, what is my comfort? They will find a way to keep the ancestral spirits alive.

If the sacred narrative cannot be in the form of a religious cosmology, it will be taken from the material history of the universe and the human species. That trend is in no way debasing. The true evolutionary epic, retold as poetry, is as intrinsically ennobling as any religious epic. Material reality discovered by science already possesses more content and grandeur than all religious cosmologies combined. The continuity of the human line has been traced through a period of deep history a thousand times as old as that conceived by the Western religions. Its study has brought new revelations of great moral importance. It has made us realize that Homo sapiens is far more than an assortment of tribes and races. We are a single gene pool from which individuals are drawn in each generation and into which they are dissolved the next generation, forever united as a species by heritage and a common future. Such are the conceptions, based on fact, from which new intimations of immortality can be drawn and a new mythos evolved.

Which world view prevails, religious transcendentalism or scientific empiricism, will make a great difference in the way humanity claims the future. While the matter is under advisement, an accommodation can be reached if the following overriding facts are realized. Ethics and religion are still too complex for present-day science to explain in depth. They are, however, far more a product of autonomous evolution than has hitherto been conceded by most theologians. Science faces in ethics and religion its most interesting and possibly most humbling challenge, while religion must somehow find the way to incorporate the discoveries of science in order to retain credibility. Religion will possess strength to the extent that it codifies and puts into enduring, poetic form the highest values of humanity consistent with empirical knowledge. That is the only way to provide compelling moral leadership. Blind faith, no matter how passionately expressed, will not suffice. Science, for its part, will test relentlessly every assumption about the human condition and in time uncover the bedrock of moral and religious sentiments.

The eventual result of the competition between the two world views, I believe, will be the secularization of the human epic and of religion itself. However the process plays out, it demands open discussion and unwavering intellectual rigor in an atmosphere of mutual respect.


Growing cabbage in home gardens

Cabbage is a member of the mustard family and, like most related crops, grows best in cool weather.

The crop has round, flattened or pointed heads made of leaves that wrap around each other tightly. In the center of the head is a short, thick stem or “core.”

Cabbage has many uses in the kitchen. Raw, it brings crunch and zest to salads and slaw. You can braise, stir-fry, stuff, add to soups, mix into the filling for egg rolls, and ferment cabbage to make sauerkraut and kimchi.

In Minnesota, you can plant cabbage in spring for a summer crop, and again in mid-summer for a fall crop.

Soil pH and fertility

Soil testing and fertilizer

  • Many Minnesota soils have adequate amounts of phosphorus.
  • Unless your soil test report specifically recommends additional phosphorus, use a low- or no-phosphorus fertilizer.
  • Spread the fertilizer in a six-inch wide band, and scratch it into the surface of the soil.
  • If you use manure or compost, you may not need additional fertilizer applications, depending on how much organic matter you apply.

Planting

Start cabbage indoors if you will plant it in the spring for a summer harvest. Although the seeds will germinate at low soil temperatures, cabbage seedlings are sensitive to frost. If you wait until the weather has settled, and plant the seeds later in spring, the crop will mature during the hottest part of the summer, leading to poor quality.

There is no need to use a heating mat as you might for other seeds. Normal room temperatures between 60°F and 70°F, and bright overhead light, will lead to the best development of the plants. Higher temperatures cause rapid growth, producing tall, weak plants that are difficult to handle without causing damage.

  1. Start seeds indoors in early April, or four to six weeks before transplanting. Leave 24 to 30 inches between hand-cultivated rows, and 18 inches between plants. Per 20 feet of row, you should order one seed packet, or 12 plants.
  2. Plant the seeding at a depth of 1/4 of an inch.
  3. Apply fertilizer to developing seedlings beginning when the first true leaf appears. Use a half-strength starter solution once a week. After two true leaves are present, apply fertilizer twice a week.
  4. When the plants have five true leaves after about three weeks, reduce watering.
  5. Place plants outside where they will receive a couple of hours of sunlight and have wind protection.
  6. Slowly expose them to more sunlight over the next week or two, bringing them indoors if night temperatures drop below 40°F.
  7. Dig small holes with a trowel, or dig a furrow with a shovel.
  8. Place the seedlings 15 to 18 inches apart, and fill the soil around them so that the plant is at the same level it was in its pot.
  9. Water the plants in, or use a transplant starter solution high in phosphorus, and low in nitrogen and potassium.

For a fall crop, plant seed directly in the garden in early July. It is impossible to know just when cold weather will come, but in most of Minnesota, you must harvest cold-tolerant crops like cabbage by late October.

Cabbage takes between 60 and 100 days to mature. A July planting will begin to form a head as summer turns to fall, and be ready to harvest before a hard freeze. Direct seeded cabbages will take up to three weeks longer to reach maturity than transplants, so for much of Minnesota, the first week in July is the right time to plant.


Watch the video: 3 x zelí: kysané, bílé, červené (October 2022).